Orientalism,
Occidentalism and Relativism
Proximity
of strangers in the era of globalization
Roy
Voragen, M.A., M.A.[1]
FIB-UI
– 5 November 2008
Globalization
is not something abstract, it is concrete (and its consequences are real).
Globalization is not out there, it is here (and now). Globalization is not
metaphysical, it is political (because its consequences are real and public). While
the consequences of globalization are obviously uneven, that, on the other
hand, does not mean that people have merely to accept these consequences
passively without any ability to alter, appropriate and acculturate.
There is nothing teleological about globalization.
History has no purpose and the future is not inevitable. We are not progressing
towards a situation where we will all be members of a single civilization,
where all peoples of the world will embrace liberal democracy and market
capitalism. Not only is globalization not a given its consequences are unequal
and not benign (and can be bellicose).
Globalization
has impacts on every one, but not equally. Globalization, writes Beck, are “the
processes through which sovereign
national states are criss-crossed and undermined by transnational actors with
varying prospects of power, orientation, identities and networks.”[2]
Globalization,
Anthony Giddens writes, is a “[g]rowing interdependence between different
peoples, regions and countries in the world as social and economic
relationships come to stretch worldwide.”[3]
Giddens sees modernity spreading across the globe as globalization progresses.[4]
Modernization in the era of globalization is not the same as Westernization or
homogenization[5]
(hybridization is the keyword). Modernization becomes pluralized;[6]
globalization thus means a move away from universalism.[7]
Modernity in the era of globalization is not linear and not singular. The
Enlightenment hope for progress and historical inevitability is utopian.
Moreover, the Enlightenment dream of a universal civilization is Eurocentric.[8]
A growing interconnectedness and interdependence does not necessarily lead to
peaceful cooperation; globalization does not mean an end to all international
political conflicts, interstate war remains an immanent possibility.
Space and time are
being compressed; we can go across space within no time. Activities can occur
or experienced simultaneously around the globe. This does not mean that space
is no longer of significance, how could we be and act without it? Space is the
precondition to all existence, action and interaction. We, to state the obvious,
live spatially. Territory is still important and we can see a dialectic between
the local and the global. Globalization is thus still spatially constituted,
however, the meaning of distance and proximity changes in a world where people,
values and goods are mobile. I can be socially near to someone, but that person
can be spatially distant (or the other way around).
Globalization is
not a one-way process people have to undergo passively, but, of course, not
every one has the same power to alter and appropriate these social changes. We
are connected in many ways, economics is only one way. Globalization should not be seen as something ‘out there’, it
is also an ‘in here’ matter.
Globalization “affects, or rather is dialectically related to, even the most
intimate aspects of our lives.”[9]
Globalization restructures space, what Giddens calls ‘action at distance’ is
the possibility to act without being present. ‘Action at distance’ is a two-way
process, globalization is without ‘direction’ and we can no longer speak of
globalization as Westernization. No one is outside, and while for a long time,
the ‘conversation’ went only from the West to the ‘other’ now “mutual
interrogation is possible.”[10]
With ‘mutual interrogation’ (for example the ongoing debate on post-colonialism
and neo-imperialism) not only come all sorts of forms of (violent) resistance,
but also a possibility for all sides to mutually change.
One such
interrogation to resist is the three-decade-old book ‘Orientalism’ by
Palestinian-American Edward Said. The illegitimate invasion of Iraq by the
United States – by ignoring the United Nations and the territorial integrity of
the people of Iraq – makes that this book did not loose any of its power.
What Said calls
Orientalism is an Orient based on the experiences of Westerners. Orientalism is
a discourse to make a dividing line between ‘us and them’, between those who
are included in the making of history and civilization and those who are not.
For this Said borrows from Michel Foucault and Antonio Gramsci. From Foucault
he borrows the term discourse and from Gramsci the term hegemony. Orientalism
is an academic, intellectual and cultural discourse that helps to sustain the
economic, political and militaristic hegemony of among others the United States.
According to Said,
borrowing from Giovanni Battista Vico, “the Orient is not an inert fact of
nature. It is not merely there, just
as the Occident itself is not just there
either. […M]en make their own history, that what they can know is what they have
made, and extend it to geography: as both geographical and cultural entities –
to say nothing of historical entities [such as nation-states] – such locales,
regions, geographical sectors as ‘Orient’ and ‘Occident’ are man-made.”[11]
However, Said continues, these ideas on space have real consequences for power
relations in our global society.
Through Orientalism the Orient becomes ‘Orientalized’, so
that the Occident can dominate the Orient. Orientalism is not merely a set of
myths that can be removed by revealing the truth. Orientalism is a hegemonic
discourse about the Orient to hold power over the Orient. “Orientalism depends
for its strategy on this flexible positional
superiority, which puts the Westerner in a whole series of possible
relationships with the Orient without ever losing him the relative upper hand.”[12]
Said is not saying that only women
can write about women (men can be feminists, J.S. Mill and Amartya Sen are
examples), or only homosexuals about homosexuals, or only blacks about blacks,
or only Indonesians about Indonesians, or only Muslims about Islam. Said writes
that “there is a difference between knowledge of other peoples and other times
that is the result of understanding, compassion, careful study and analysis for
their own sakes, and on the other hand knowledge – if that is what it is – that
is part of an overall campaign of self-affirmation, belligerency, and out-right
war. There is, after all, a profound difference between the will to understand
for purposes of coexistence and humanistic enlargement of horizons, and the
will to dominate for the purposes of control and external enlargement of
horizons, and the will to dominate for the purposes of control and external
domination.”[13]
Said’s
book ‘Orientalism’ is about how Westerners perceive the Orient and how this
body of knowledge is used in a power structure. This book is not about the
Orient in general or about the Arab and Islamic world in particular. This book
is also not an anti-Western book. In the Islamic world, so says Said, this book
is read as such. Said calls this ‘Occidentosis’, which means that Muslims claim
that “all the evils in the world come from the west.”[14]
The Dutch-British
Ian Buruma and the Israeli Avishai Margalit write in the conclusion of
‘Occidentalism’: “The story we have told in this book is not a Manichaeistic
one of a civilization at war with another. On the contrary, it is a tale of
cross-contamination, the spread of bad ideas. This could happen to us now, if
we fall for the temptation to fight fire with fire, Islamism with our own forms
of intolerance. Religious authority, especially in the United States, is
already having a dangerous influence on political governance. We cannot afford
to close our societies as a defense against those who have closed theirs. For
then we would all become Occidentalists, and there would be nothing left to
defend.”[15]
‘Orientalism’ by the Palestinian Edward Said and Buruma
and Margalit’s ‘Occidentalism, The West in the Eyes of its Enemies’ are about
those people who see the other as different, unlike them, less than human, i.e.
these are dehumanizing ideologies, which reduces human individuals to sub-human
classes, which, in turn, can lead to the destruction of human lives.
The Orientalist sees the other as the ‘lazy native’, as the
‘exotic savant’ (often pictured in erotic and feminized terms). The native is
backward because of his irrationality, and this justifies colonialism and
imperialism. Colonialism and imperialism are justified because they are
civilizational forces, so the argument goes.
Orientalism is as one-dimensional as Occidentalism, but
now it dehumanizes not the peoples of the Orient but the peoples of the
Occident. Both ideologies have real and violent consequences. September 11,
2001, is an example where a dislike of the West took a very wrong turn. Buruma
and Margalit’s book is an attempt to understand those fanatics who hijacked
airplanes that destroyed the WTC in New York on an early September morning that
reset the mood for this millennium.[16]
It is the spiritual and profound East versus the coldly
mechanical, shallow, rootless, destructive, sex-obsessed, and materialistic
West. Today Occidentalists often focus at the U.S., “anti-Americanism is
sometimes the result of specific American policies […]. But whatever the U.S.
government does or does not do is often beside the point. [… Occidentalism
refers] not to American policies, but to the idea of America itself, as a
rootless, cosmopolitan, superficial, trivial, materialistic, racially-mixed,
fashion-addicted civilization.”[17]
How to deal with disagreement, indeterminacy, inconsistency,
incoherence, incongruity, ambivalence, heterogeneity, opacity, paradoxy, and
uncertainty. Nietzsche is the philosopher that warned us that ontological
uncertainty causes anxiety,[18]
and possibly violence against the ‘stranger’, against what is ‘alien’.
According to Zygmunt Bauman the task of philosophy today is to teach us how to
deal with uncertainty and contingency. The search for absolute and universal
values, though, is the existential need for security.[19]
Where in a traditional society the stranger would live on the other side of the
border, today we no longer have that luxury.
Some long back to a traditional society, for it gives
ontological security a society in present-day modernity cannot provide, with
all the anxiety consequently. In a pre-modern society the question what a
society is remains unasked. Within a tradition a person lives in a
pre-established order. In modernity the individual has to ask the questions how
society should be ordered. We can no longer rely on pre-established answers for
these questions.
Modernity held the promise that we could find security
in rationality. However, modernity is now primarily characterized by insecurity
and instability. Radical doubt is turned against itself: how could radical
doubt lead to certain and stable knowledge with which we could colonize the
future? Many dangers we face in this world are manufactured by ourselves. Many
things cannot be given, that makes calculating risks impossible.
We can know how to act if we are able to understand a
situation. Indeterminacy makes global society a risk-prone environment. A high
risk environment can lead to anxiety and alienation. We live in an ambivalent
territory, as Bauman writes: “life is carried on by strangers among strangers.”[20]
This can make life fragmentary. Bauman states that there is a gap between what
we need to know how to act and what we can know how to act among people we
perceive as ‘strange’. Freedom is no longer feasible when fear takes over.
The individual has to negotiate the proximity of
differences. The stranger is near but socially distant. The high mobility in
present-day modernity makes this situation even more complex. The danger is a
renewed longing for communityhood – a community of thick relations of care – to
exclude the stranger.
Now it is time to discuss the problem of relativism.
Stereotyping – as done by Occidentalists and Orientalists – does not help
communication, and, as we will see, relativism also does not help communication.
The problem of relativism can be discussed from the perspective of epistemology
and morality. I will first discuss the epistemological perspective briefly
before elaborating on the moral perspective on relativism.
Epistemological
relativism concerns the problem of the mind. How am I justified to claim that
the mind of someone else works in the same way as my mind? After all, I do not
have psychic powers to read minds. That someone else’s mind works by analogy to
my mind presupposes that the other is similar to me.[21]
From a logical perspective it might be possible to talk about and act in the
reality in the same way while perceiving it in a very different ways in our
mind. It is not necessary that the mental states of our minds correspond with
our behavior. A way out of this problem is through the use of the
Wittgensteinian games, i.e. intersubjective meanings come necessarily prior to
subjective meanings. If I want to understand (or predict) the behavior of
someone I have to look at her or his part in a certain game.
That
brings us to the moral problem of cultural relativism. There is an old saying:
‘In Rome behave as the Romans do.’ Does that mean there is no room for
universal values that cross the boundaries of space and time? One such
universal value could be respect for human life. However, the debates
concerning abortion, euthanasia, and the death penalty seem to show that we do
not have a consensus on the question what constitutes man. What is then the
normative source of morality if our moral values and norms merely reflect the
cultural conventions of a certain space and time?
The
anthropologist Clifford Geertz, who wrote extensively on Indonesia, defines
culture as “an historically transmitted pattern of meanings embodied in
symbols, a system of inherited conceptions expressed in symbolic forms by means
of which men communicate, perpetuate, and develop their knowledge about and
attitudes toward life.”[22]
And indeed, different cultures do have different moral values and norms. What
can be seen as right in one culture can be perceived as wrong in another, and
it is then naïve to assume that our norms have universal validity.
Cultural
relativists assume that there are no universal truths in ethics, i.e. that
every normative standard can only be applied within a culture. According to
James Rachels cultural relativists distinguish six claims:
1.
“Different societies have
different moral codes.”
2.
There is no objective standard
that can be used to judge one social code better than another.”
3.
“The moral code of our own
society has no special status; it is merely one among many.”
4.
“There is no ‘universal truth’ in
ethics – that is, there are no moral truths that hold for all peoples at all
times.”
5.
“The moral code of a society
determines what is right within that society; that is, if the moral code of a
society says that a certain action is right, then that is right, at least within that society.”
6.
“It is mere arrogance for us to
try to judge the conduct of other peoples. We should adopt an attitude of
tolerance toward the practices of other cultures.”[23]
We should,
according to Rachels, first look at the form of argument cultural relativists
are making. Cultural relativists conclude from the fact that there are cultural
differences that we also cannot find agreement on morality. Rachels calls this
the ‘cultural difference argument’. “The premise concerns what people believe […]. The conclusion, however,
concerns what really is the case.”[24]
This argument is therefore logically fallacious. As if the simple point that we
disagree means there is no true position to be found.
But what
if we would take cultural relativism seriously? What are the consequences if we
do not have a normative point of view from outside a certain culture? The first
consequence is that we can no longer perceive cultural practices as morally
inferior to our own practices, i.e. we have no longer a tool for moral
criticism (in the debates on human rights and Asian values this position is
often taken, criticism is then not seen as enlightened but as a new tool for of
imperialism). Second, we can only judge our society by the standards of our own
society. So even when we know that our society is not perfect we have no tools
to morally improve it. And third, moral relativism not only makes criticism
impossible, it also makes moral progress infeasible. Relativism does not give
us a standard to judge something as being better or improved, that makes social
reform impossible.
According
to Rachels, cultural relativism overestimates our differences. “The difference
is in our belief systems, not in our values. […] We cannot conclude, then,
merely because our customs differ, that there is a disagreement about values.”[25]
All societies must have something in common for them to exist. Rachels gives
two examples: lying and murder must be the exception to the rule for societies
to function.
Cultural
relativism is popular, so there must be something that can be learned from it.
The first lesson to be learned is to warn us against arrogance that our moral
values are based on an absolute rational standard and therefore ultimately
better than other moral systems. Many of our values are indeed products of our
cultural conventions. The second lesson to be learned is that cultural
relativism warns us against prejudices. One such prejudice is against
homosexuality. Many perceive homosexuality as immoral,
but we cannot conclude from there that homosexuality is illegal. According to
John Stuart Mill we should separate the law from other categories, such as
morality, aesthetic criticism, etiquette, tradition, customs, and convention.
Cultural relativism criticizes thus the dogmatism of universalism.
The French Calvinist Pierre Bayle (1647-1706), for
instance, writes: “Education is undoubtedly capable of making clarity of truths
of right utterly fade away. […] The same force […] which makes a Turkish child
believe that the Koran is a holy book, would have made him believe the same
regarding the Bible, if he therefore
been turned in that direction; from whence it arises that if that force
was bad in the Turkish child, it would be in the Christian child.”[26]
Eurocentrism is parochial, it takes Europe as the center of the world. Michel
de Montaigne (1533-1592) explains this when he writes: “Man is always inclined
to regard the small circle in which he lives as the center of the world and to
make his particular, private life the standard of the universe and to make his
particular, private life the standard of the universe. But he must give up this
vain pretense, this petty provincial way of thinking and judging.”[27]
Rachels’
discussion of cultural relativism overlooks the fact that all modern societies
have to deal with diversity. Pluralism and rational
disagreement about the truth are common features in today’s societies.[28]
Indonesia is no different from that perspective. “The question of how to
achieve civility and inclusive citizenship in deeply plural societies is today
a near-universal one.”[29]
The theory that applies cultural relativism to a society is known as
multiculturalism.[30]
Multiculturalism has two major flaws (beside the ones we
discussed above). First, just as the world cannot be divided into homogenous
civilizations, so can a society not be divided into homogenous blocks of
separate cultures. Global society is one
of overlapping territories and interdependent histories according to Said. For
example, Indonesia cannot easily be divided in Muslim, Catholic, Protestant,
Hindu, Buddhist and Confucianist cultures. And second, multiculturalism locks
individuals up in separate cultures by reducing their identity to a singular
identity. For example, an Indonesian is not only a Muslim but can also be poor,
Sundanese, angkot driver, fan of Persib and dangdut, a father, a husband, etc.
The Nobel Prize-winner Amartya Sen wants to make clear
in his latest book ‘Identity and Violence’ that nations are not diverse because
they are federations of peoples, each nation, on the other hand, is a
collection of individual citizens and each individual inhibits a wide range of
identities. Sen writes that he “can be, at the same time, an Asian, an Indian
citizen, a Bengali with Bangladeshi ancestry, an American or British resident,
an economist, a dabbler in philosophy, an author, a Sanskritist, a strong
believer in secularism and democracy, a man, a feminist, a heterosexual, a
defender of gay and lesbian rights, with a nonreligious lifestyle, from a Hindu
background, a non-Brahmin, and a non-believer in an afterlife (and also […] in
a ‘before-life’ as well).”[31]
It depends on the context, according to Sen, which part gets focus. No matter
how constraint we are by circumstances, we still have to choose and for making
choices we need to reason, i.e. to give arguments and justifications.
Identity is a complicated matter. And identity matters.
Identity matters for the way we are, think, and act. “When we shift our
attention from the notion of being
identical to oneself to that of sharing
an identity with others of a particular group […], the complexity increases
further.”[32]
Huntington wrote an influential book on group-belonging, titled ‘Clash of
Civilizations’.[33]
Huntington is right to claim that there are differences between East and West,
but he makes those differences too pronounced, there exist considerable
overlap. And not civilizations can clash, persons can, and a person is never
only a Muslim, nor is one Muslim a representation of Islam as such (there is no
Islam as such, that is false essentialism). “Civilizational or religious
partitioning of the world population yields a ‘solitarist’ approach to human
identity.”[34]
We all have plural identities according to Sen and he
claims that it depends on a particular context which part is most important.
“When the prospects of good relations among different human beings are seen […]
primarily in terms of ‘amity among civilizations’, or ‘dialogue between
religious groups’, or ‘friendly relations between different communities’ […], a
serious miniaturization of human beings precedes the devised programs of
peace.”[35]
As a slogan ‘bhinneka
tunggal ika’ (unity in diversity) has the danger of denying diversity and thus
the freedom of individual citizens. The emphasis on the
oneness is a matter of establishing a unity where diversity is and where
potential social unrest lingers. Thus while diversity is an empirical fact in
Indonesia, these diverse phenomena are only seen as representations of the one
and only. The ‘grand design’ becomes then more important than particular lives
of individual citizens: “In diversity is unity; all phenomena are
miniaturizations of the essential features of the universe.”[36]
Of course, freedom can only exist in a safe and civilized society, but we
should not too easily restrict freedom in the name of safety and security.[37]
The Indonesian Muslim Scholars Council (‘Majelis Ulama
Indonesia – MUI’)[38]
is very critical of cultural relativism and multiculturalism. In 2005 MUI
issued a fatwa (religious decree) declaring pluralism haram (unlawful). While MUI acknowledges
that a plurality of religions is a fact of life in Indonesia, pluralism is
unlawful, because pluralism denies religious truth by seeing religions on an
equal footing, hence relativism, which denies religious truth. However, from an
epistemological point of view all religions are equal, no religion can proof it
is more true than other religions.[39]
Society is a ‘collection’ of strangers; acknowledging
this fact is an important step to the cosmopolitanization of urban society. Cosmopolitanization entails
pluralization and hybridization instead of homogenization. The wider world
becomes a part of society.
Resisting
ambiguity can lead to violence: “someone who affirms and elevates ‘his own’
will almost inevitably rejects and despises the foreign.”[40]
Prejudices are reflections of fear.
We need discussions concerning inclusive citizenship (prebumi vs. non-prebumi), freedom (the anti-pornography law) and tolerance. (the
case of the Ahmadya sect).
If these discussions are going to be(-come) civilized
ones then we should agree on at least thing first: we should agree that we can
disagree.
[1] He teaches philosophy and politics at
Parahyangan Catholic University, Bandung; he can be contacted at royvoragen@hotmail.com,
and his weblog can be
accessed at http://fatumbrutum.blogspot.com/. This essay was presented as a
guest lecture at University of Indonesia’s Department of Arabic Language and
Culture, Depok, November 5, 2005.
[2] See p11, Beck, U., What is Globalization?, Cambridge: Polity Press,
2003.
[3] See p690, Giddens, A., Sociology, Cambridge: Polity Press, 2001.
[4] See p63, p177, Giddens, A., The Consequences of Modernity, Cambridge:
Polity Press, 1990. Giddens defines modernity as “to refer to institutions and
modes of behavior established first of all in post-feudal Europe, but which in
the twentieth century increasingly have become world-historical in impact.
‘Modernity’ can be understood as roughly equivalent to ‘the industrialized
world’, so long as it be recognized that industrialism is not its only
institutional dimension. […] A second dimension is capitalism […]. Each of
these can be distinguished analytically from the institutions of surveillance
[…]. This dimension can in turn be separated from control of the means of
violence in the context of the ‘industrialization of war’.” See pp14-5,
Giddens, A., Modernity and Self-Identity, Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991.
[5] Benjamin Barber, for example, claims that Coca Cola pushes tea of the
market in Indonesia. The Indonesian company Sosro is very successful though.
Instead of McDonaldization and Coca Colanization we can see an increase of
diversity. See Barber, B.R., Jihad vs. McWorld, Terrorism’s Challenge to
Democracy, London: Corgi Books, 2003.
[6] See p3, Beck, U., World Risk Society, Cambridge: Polity Press, 2003.
[7] See p14, p19, Therborn, G., ‘At the birth of second century sociology:
times of reflexivity, spaces of identity, and nodes of knowledge’, in: British Journal of Sociology, Vol.51,
no.1 (January/March 2000): pp37-57.
[8] See p170, Gray, J., False Dawn, The Delusions of Global Capitalism,
London: Granta, 2002.
[9] See p95, Giddens, A., ‘Living in a Post-Traditional Society’, in:
Beck, U., Giddens, A., Lash, S., Reflexive Modernization, Politics, Tradition,
and Aesthetics in the Modern Social Order, Stanford: Stanford University Press,
1994. See also Giddens, The Transformation of Intimacy, Sexuality, Love, and
Eroticism in Modern Societies, Cambridge: Polity Press, 2002.
[10] See pp 96-7, Giddens, A., ‘Living in a Post-Traditional Society’.
[11] See pp4-5, Said, E.W., Orientalism, New York: Vintage Books, 1994.
[12] See p7, idem.
[13] See pxix, idem.
[14] See p221, Said, E.W., ‘Orientalsim and After’, in: Viswanathan, G.
(ed.), Power, Politics and Culture, Interviews with Edward W. Said, London:
Bloomsbury, 2004.
[15] See p149, Buruma, I., Margalit, A., Occidentalism, The West in the
Eyes of its Enemies, New York: Penguin Books, 2004.
[16] Portions of their book were published as an essay: ‘Occidentalism’,
in: The New York Review of Books
(January 17, 2002).
[17] See p8, Buruma, I., Margalit, A., Occidentalism.
[18] See pp32-3, Davies, T., Humanism, New York: Routledge, 1997.
[19] See p81-2, Bauman, Z., Modernity and Ambivalence, Cambridge: Polity
Press, 1991.
[20] See p125, Bauman, Z., Life in Fragments, Essays in Postmodern
Morality, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1995.
[21] See p226, Hollis, M., The Philosophy of Social Science, an
Introduction, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
[22] See p89, Geertz, C., The Interpretation of Cultures, Basic Books,
1973.
[23] See p18, Rachels, J., The Elements of Moral Philosophy, New York:
McGraw-Hill, 1995.
[24] See p19, idem.
[25] See p23, idem.
[26] Quoted on pp49-50, Mori, G., ‘Pierre Bayle, The Rights of the
Conscience, the ‘Remedy’ of Toleration’, in: Ratio Juris, Vol,10, no.1 (March 1997): pp45-60.
[27] Quoted on p14, Cassirer, E., An essay on man, An introduction to a
philosophy of human culture, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1979. Europeans
can fall in the trap of Eurocentrism, then the West is seen as the norm for
civilization (Western civilization is then a pleonasm).
[28] It would not be rational to disagree about something we actually agree
about, neither would it be rational to agree about something we actually
disagree about; see pp50-1, Larmore, C.E., Patterns of Moral Complexity,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
[29] See p4, Hefner, R.W. (ed.), The Politics of Multiculturalism,
Pluralism and Citizenship in Malaysia, Singapore, and Indonesia, Honolulu:
University Of Hawai’i Press, 2001.
[30] See Dworkin, W., Cultural Cirizenship, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2003. See also Bowen, J.R., ‘Normative Pluralism in Indonesia: Regions,
Religions, and Ethnicities’, in: Will Kymlicka and Boagang He (eds.),
Multiculturalism in Asia: Theoratical Perspectives, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2005 (this chapter can be downloaded from http://www.artsci.wustl.edu/~anthro/blurb/b_bowen.html). For a strong criticism of multiculturalism
see Barry, B., Culture and Equality, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2002.
[31] See p19, Sen, A., Identity and Violence, The Illusion of Destiny,
Princeton: W.W.Norton, 2007.
[32] See pxii, idem.
[33] Huntington, S.P., The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World
Order, New York: Simon Schuster, 1996.
[34] See pxii, Sen, A., Violence of Identity.
[35] See pxiii, idem.
[36] See p128, Stewart, S., On Longing:
Narratives of the miniature, the gigantic, the souvenir, the collection,
Baltimore: The John Hopkins University Press, 1984; quoted from p241, Spyer,
P., Belum stabil: Some Signs of the Times in Post-Soeharto Indonesia, in:
Samuel, H., Schulte Nordholt, H. (eds.), Indonesia in Transition, Rethinking
Civil Society, Region, and Crisis, Yogyakarta: Pustaka Pelajar, 2004.
[37] SARA (‘Suku, Agama, Ras, dan Antar-golongan’)
guidelines prohibit to stir up ethnic, religious, racial, or group (class)
tensions.
[38] MUI is founded in 1975 by Soeharto, but it is not clear what the legal
status is of the organization or its decrees, as Bowen asks: “Does an MUI
decree have the force of law […], or is it only advisory to the government, and
to Muslim citizens […]?” See p235, Bowen, J.R., Islam, Law and Equality in
Indonesia, An Anthropology of Public Reasoning, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2003.
[39] We have to be careful for circular arguments, where the conclusion is
supported by premises that assume the conclusion, for example: The Quran proofs
that Allah exists. The Quran is written by Alah. Therefore, Allah exists.
[40] See p38, Beck, U., ‘The Cosmopolitan Society and its Enemies’, in: Theory, Culture & Society, Vol.19,
no.1-2 (2002): pp17-44.
Tidak ada komentar:
Posting Komentar